[1] | UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE EIGHTH CIRCUIT |
[2] | No. 99-3917EM |
[3] | Keywords: cite, unpublished opinion |
[4] | August 22, 2000 |
[5] | FAYE ANASTASOFF, APPELLANT, v. UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, APPELLEE. |
[6] | Before Richard S. Arnold and Heaney, Circuit Judges,
and Magnuson, *fn1 District Judge. |
[7] | The opinion of the court was delivered by: Richard S.
Arnold, Circuit Judge. |
[8] | On Appeal from the United States District Court for the
Eastern District of Missouri. |
[9] | Submitted: May 8, 2000 |
[10] | Faye Anastasoff seeks a refund of overpaid federal
income tax. On April 13, 1996, Ms. Anastasoff mailed her refund claim to
the Internal Revenue Service for taxes paid on April 15, 1993. The
Service denied her claim under 26 U.S.C. § 6511(b), which limits
refunds to taxes paid in the three years prior to the filing of a claim.
Although her claim was mailed within this period, it was received and
filed on April 16, 1996, three years and one day after she overpaid her
taxes, one day late. In many cases, "the Mailbox Rule," 26
U.S.C. § 7502, saves claims like Ms. Anastasoff's that would have been
timely if received when mailed; they are deemed received when
postmarked. But § 7502 applies only to claims that are untimely, and
the parties agree that under 26 U.S.C. § 6511(a), which measures the
timeliness of the refund claim itself, her claim was received on time.
The issue then is whether § 7502 can be applied, for the purposes of §
6511(b)'s three-year refund limitation, to a claim that was timely under
§ 6511(a). The District Court *fn2
held that § 7502 could not apply to any part of a timely claim, and
granted judgment for the Service. On appeal, Ms. Anastasoff argues that
§ 7502 should apply whenever necessary to fulfill its remedial purpose,
i.e., to save taxpayers from the vagaries of the postal system, even
when only part of the claim is untimely. We affirm the judgment of the
District Court. |
[11] | I. |
[12] | We rejected precisely the same legal argument in
Christie v. United States, No. 91-2375MN (8th Cir. Mar. 20, 1992) (per
curiam) (unpublished). In Christie, as here, we considered a refund
claim mailed just prior to § 6511(b)'s three-year bar and received just
after. Like Ms. Anastasoff, the Christie taxpayers argued that § 7502
should operate regardless of the claim's timeliness under § 6511(a) to
save their claim under § 6511(b). We held that even if § 7502 could
apply to a timely claim, it would not help in this situation: If § 7502
were applied to the claim, it would be deemed received before the
return. But § 6511(a) provides that a claim must be submitted within
two years of overpayment if no return has yet been filed - not three
years. In other words, to save the claim under § 6511(b) only makes it
untimely under § 6511(a). Ms. Anastasoff does not attempt to
distinguish Christie. She does argue that a relevant regulation was not
cited in Christie, but the reasoning of the Christie opinion is squarely
inconsistent with the effect taxpayer desires to attribute to the
regulation. |
[13] | Although it is our
only case directly in point, Ms. Anastasoff contends that we are not
bound by Christie because it is an unpublished decision and thus not a
precedent under 8th Circuit Rule 28A(i). We disagree. We hold that the
portion of Rule 28A(i) that declares that unpublished opinions are not
precedent is unconstitutional under Article III, because it purports to
confer on the federal courts a power that goes beyond the
"judicial." |
[14] | The Rule provides: |
[15] | Unpublished opinions are not precedent and parties
generally should not cite them. When relevant to establishing the
doctrines of res judicata, collateral estoppel, or the law of the case,
however, the parties may cite any unpublished opinion. Parties may also
cite an unpublished opinion of this court if the opinion has persuasive
value on a material issue and no published opinion of this or another
court would serve as well . . .. |
[16] | Inherent in every judicial decision is a declaration
and interpretation of a general principle or rule of law. Marbury v.
Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 177-78 (1803). This declaration of law is
authoritative to the extent necessary for the decision, and must be
applied in subsequent cases to similarly situated parties. James B. Beam
Distilling Co. v. Georgia, 501 U.S. 529, 544 (1991); Cohens v. Virginia,
6 Wheat. 264, 399 (1821). These principles, which form the doctrine of
precedent, were well established and well regarded at the time this
nation was founded. The Framers of the Constitution considered these
principles to derive from the nature of judicial power, and intended
that they would limit the judicial power delegated to the courts by
Article III of the Constitution. *fn3
Accordingly, we conclude that 8th Circuit Rule 28A(i), insofar as it
would allow us to avoid the precedential effect of our prior decisions,
purports to expand the judicial power beyond the bounds of Article III,
and is therefore unconstitutional. That rule does not, therefore, free
us from our duty to follow this Court's decision in Christie. |
[17] | II. |
[18] | The doctrine of precedent was well-established by the
time the Framers gathered in Philadelphia. Morton J. Horwitz, The
Transformation of American Law: 1780-1860 8-9 (1977); J.H. Baker, An
Introduction to English Legal History 227 (1990); Sir William Holdsworth,
Case Law, 50 L.Q.R. 180 (1934). See, e.g., 1 Sir William W. Blackstone,
Commentaries on the Laws of England *69 (1765) ("it is an
established rule to abide by former precedents"). To the jurists of
the late eighteenth century (and thus by and large to the Framers), *fn4
the doctrine seemed not just well established but an immemorial custom,
the way judging had always been carried out, part of the course of the
law. *fn5 In addition, the Framers had
inherited a very favorable view of precedent from the seventeenth
century, especially through the writings and reports of Sir Edward Coke;
the assertion of the authority of precedent had been effective in past
struggles of the English people against royal usurpations, and for the
rule of law against the arbitrary power of government. *fn6
In sum, the doctrine of precedent was not merely well established; it
was the historic method of judicial decision-making, and well regarded
as a bulwark of judicial independence in past struggles for liberty. |
[19] | Modern legal scholars tend to justify the authority of
precedents on equitable or prudential grounds. *fn7
By contrast, on the eighteenth-century view (most influentially
expounded by Blackstone), the judge's duty to follow precedent derives
from the nature of the judicial power itself. *fn8
As Blackstone defined it, each exercise of the "judicial
power" requires judges "to determine the law" arising
upon the facts of the case. 3 Blackstone, Commentaries *25. "To
determine the law" meant not only choosing the appropriate legal
principle but also expounding and interpreting it, so that "the law
in that case, being solemnly declared and determined, what before was
uncertain, and perhaps indifferent, is now become a permanent rule . .
.." 1 Commentaries *69. *fn9 In
determining the law in one case, judges bind those in subsequent cases
because, although the judicial power requires judges "to determine
law" in each case, a judge is "sworn to determine, not
according to his own judgments, but according to the known laws. [Judges
are] not delegated to pronounce a new law, but to maintain and expound
the old." Id. The judicial power to determine law is a power only
to determine what the law is, not to invent it. Because precedents are
the "best and most authoritative" guide of what the law is,
the judicial power is limited by them. Id. The derivation of
precedential authority from the law-declaring nature of the judicial
power was also familiar to the Framers through the works of Sir Edward
Coke and Sir Matthew Hale. See 4 E. Coke, Institutes of the Laws of
England 138 (1642) (a prior judicial decision on point is sufficient
authority on a question of law because "a judicial decision is to
the same extent a declaration of the law."); 1 Coke, Institutes 51
(1642) ("[i]t is the function of a judge not to make, but to
declare the law, according to the golden mete-wand of the law and not by
the crooked cord of discretion."); Sir Matthew Hale, The History of
The Common Law of England 44-45 (Univ. of Chicago ed., 1971)
("Judicial Decisions [have their] Authority in Expounding,
Declaring, and Publishing what the Law of this Kingdom is . . .."). |
[20] | In addition to keeping the law stable, this doctrine is
also essential, according to Blackstone, for the separation of
legislative and judicial power. In his discussion of the separation of
governmental powers, Blackstone identifies this limit on the
"judicial power," i.e., that judges must observe established
laws, as that which separates it from the "legislative" power
and in which "consists one main preservative of public
liberty." 1 Blackstone, Commentaries *258-59. If judges had the
legislative power to "depart from" established legal
principles, "the subject would be in the hands of arbitrary judges,
whose decisions would be then regulated only by their own opinions . .
.." Id. at *259. |
[21] | The Framers accepted this understanding of judicial
power (sometimes referred to as the declaratory theory of adjudication)
and the doctrine of precedent implicit in it. *fn10
Hamilton, like Blackstone, recognized that a court "pronounces the
law" arising upon the facts of each case. *fn11
The Federalist No. 81, at 531 (Alexander Hamilton) (Modern Library ed.,
1938). He explained the law-declaring concept of judicial power in the
term, "jurisdiction": "This word is composed of JUS and
DICTIO, juris dictio, or a speaking and pronouncing of the law,"
id., and concluded that the jurisdiction of appellate courts, as a
law-declaring power, is not antagonistic to the fact-finding role of
juries. Id. Like Blackstone, he thought that "[t]he courts must
declare the sense of the law," and that this fact means courts must
exercise "judgment" about what the law is rather than
"will" about what it should be. The Federalist No. 78 507-08.
Like Blackstone, he recognized that this limit on judicial
decision-making is a crucial sign of the separation of the legislative
and judicial power. Id. at 508. Hamilton concludes that "[t]o avoid
an arbitrary discretion in the courts, it is indispensable that they
should be bound down by strict rules and precedents, which serve to
define and point out their duty in every particular case that comes
before them . . .." Id. at 510. *fn12 |
[22] | The Framers thought that, under the Constitution,
judicial decisions would become binding precedents in subsequent cases.
Hamilton anticipated that the record of federal precedents "must
unavoidably swell to a very considerable bulk. . . ." Id. But
precedents were not to be recorded for their own sake. He expected
judges to give them "long and laborious study" and to have a
"competent knowledge of them." Id. Likewise, Madison
recognized "the obligation arising from judicial expositions of the
law on succeeding judges." Letter from James Madison to Charles
Jared Ingersoll (June 25, 1831), reprinted in The Mind of the Founder:
Sources of the Political Thought of James Madison 390, 390-93 (Marvin
Meyers ed., rev. ed. 1981). Madison expected that the accumulation of
precedents would be beneficial: "[a]mong other difficulties, the
exposition of the Constitution is frequently a copious source, and must
continue so until its meaning on all great points shall have been
settled by precedents." Letter from James Madison to Samuel Johnson
(June 21, 1789), in 12 Papers of James Madison 250 (Robert A. Rutland et
al. eds., 1977). Although they drew different conclusions from the fact,
the Anti-Federalists also assumed that federal judicial decisions would
become authorities in subsequent cases. *fn13
Finally, early Americans demonstrated the authority which they assigned
to judicial decisions by rapidly establishing a reliable system of
American reporters in the years following the ratification of the
Constitution. Grant Gilmore, The Ages of American Law 23 (1977); Peter
Karsten, Heart Versus Head: Judge-Made Law in Nineteenth-Century America
28-32 (1997). |
[23] | We do not mean to suggest that the Framers expected or
intended the publication (in the sense of being printed in a book) of
all opinions. For the Framers, limited publication of judicial decisions
was the rule, and they never drew that practice into question. Before
the ratification of the Constitution, there was almost no private
reporting and no official reporting at all in the American states.
Frederick G. Kempin, Jr., Precedent and Stare Decisis: The Critical
Years, 1800-1850, 3 Am. J. Leg. Hist. 28, 34 (1959) (reviewing the
history of American reports). As we have seen, however, the Framers did
not regard this absence of a reporting system as an impediment to the
precedential authority of a judicial decision. Although they lamented
the problems associated with the lack of a reporting system and worked
to assure more systematic reporting, judges and lawyers of the day
recognized the authority of unpublished decisions even when they were
established only by memory or by a lawyer's unpublished memorandum.
Karsten, Heart Versus Head 30; Jesse Root, The Origin of Government and
Laws in Connecticut (1798), reprinted in The Legal Mind in American
38-39 (Perry Miller ed., 1962). *fn14 |
[24] | To summarize, in the late eighteenth century, the
doctrine of precedent was well-established in legal practice (despite
the absence of a reporting system), regarded as an immemorial custom,
and valued for its role in past struggles for liberty. The duty of
courts to follow their prior decisions was understood to derive from the
nature of the judicial power itself and to separate it from a dangerous
union with the legislative power. The statements of the Framers indicate
an understanding and acceptance of these principles. We conclude
therefore that, as the Framers intended, the doctrine of precedent
limits the "judicial power" delegated to the courts in Article
III. No less an authority than Justice (Professor) Joseph Story is in
accord. See his Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States
§§ 377-78 (1833): |
[25] | The case is not alone considered as decided and
settled; but the principles of the decision are held, as precedents and
authority, to bind future cases of the same nature. This is the constant
practice under our whole system of jurisprudence. Our ancestors brought
it with them, when they first emigrated to this country; and it is, and
always has been considered, as the great security of our rights, our
liberties, and our property. It is on this account, that our law is
justly deemed certain, and founded in permanent principles, and not
dependent upon the caprice or will of judges. A more alarming doctrine
could not be promulgated by any American court, than that it was at
liberty to disregard all former rules and decisions, and to decide for
itself, without reference to the settled course of antecedent
principles. |
[26] | This known course of proceeding, this settled habit of
thinking, this conclusive effect of judicial adjudications, was in the
full view of the framers of the constitution. It was required, and
enforced in every state in the Union; and a departure from it would have
been justly deemed an approach to tyranny and arbitrary power, to the
exercise of mere discretion, and to the abandonment of all the just
checks upon judicial authority. |
[27] | III. |
[28] | Before concluding, we wish to indicate what this case
is not about. It is not about whether opinions should be published,
whether that means printed in a book or available in some other
accessible form to the public in general. Courts may decide, for one
reason or another, that some of their cases are not important enough to
take up pages in a printed report. Such decisions may be eminently
practical and defensible, but in our view they have nothing to do with
the authoritative effect of any court decision. The question presented
here is not whether opinions ought to be published, but whether they
ought to have precedential effect, whether published or not. We point
out, in addition, that "unpublished" in this context has never
meant "secret." So far as we are aware, every opinion and
every order of any court in this country, at least of any appellate
court, is available to the public. You may have to walk into a clerk's
office and pay a per-page fee, but you can get the opinion if you want
it. Indeed, most appellate courts now make their opinions, whether
labeled "published" or not, available to anyone on line. This
is true of our Court. |
[29] | Another point about the practicalities of the matter
needs to be made. It is often said among judges that the volume of
appeals is so high that it is simply unrealistic to ascribe precedential
value to every decision. We do not have time to do a decent enough job,
the argument runs, when put in plain language, to justify treating every
opinion as a precedent. If this is true, the judicial system is indeed
in serious trouble, but the remedy is not to create an underground body
of law good for one place and time only. The remedy, instead, is to
create enough judgeships to handle the volume, or, if that is not
practical, for each judge to take enough time to do a competent job with
each case. If this means that backlogs will grow, the price must still
be paid. At bottom, rules like our Rule 28A(i) assert that courts have
the following power: to choose for themselves, from among all the cases
they decide, those that they will follow in the future, and those that
they need not. Indeed, some forms of the non-publication rule even
forbid citation. Those courts are saying to the bar: "We may have
decided this question the opposite way yesterday, but this does not bind
us today, and, what's more, you cannot even tell us what we did
yesterday." As we have tried to explain in this opinion, such a
statement exceeds the judicial power, which is based on reason, not
fiat. |
[30] | Finally, lest we be misunderstood, we stress that we
are not here creating some rigid doctrine of eternal adherence to
precedents. Cases can be overruled. Sometimes they should be. On our
Court, this function can be performed by the en banc Court, but not by a
single panel. If the reasoning of a case is exposed as faulty, or if
other exigent circumstances justify it, precedents can be changed. When
this occurs, however, there is a burden of justification. The precedent
from which we are departing should be stated, and our reasons for
rejecting it should be made convincingly clear. In this way, the law
grows and changes, but it does so incrementally, in response to the
dictates of reason, and not because judges have simply changed their
minds. |
[31] | IV. |
[32] | For these reasons, we must reject Ms. Anastasoff's
argument that, under 8th Cir. R. 28A(i), we may ignore our prior
decision in Christie. Federal courts, in adopting rules, are not free to
extend the judicial power of the United States described in Article III
of the Constitution. Willy v. Coastal Corp., 503 U.S. 131, 135 (1992).
The judicial power of the United States is limited by the doctrine of
precedent. Rule 28A(i) allows courts to ignore this limit. If we mark an
opinion as unpublished, Rule 28A(i) provides that is not precedent.
Though prior decisions may be well-considered and directly on point,
Rule 28A(i) allows us to depart from the law set out in such prior
decisions without any reason to differentiate the cases. This discretion
is completely inconsistent with the doctrine of precedent; even in
constitutional cases, courts "have always required a departure from
precedent to be supported by some 'special justification.' " United
States v. International Business Machines Corp., 517 U.S. 843, 856
(1996), quoting Payne v. Tennessee, 501 U.S. 808, 842 (1991) (Souter,
J., concurring). Rule 28A(i) expands the judicial power beyond the
limits set by Article III by allowing us complete discretion to
determine which judicial decisions will bind us and which will not.
Insofar as it limits the precedential effect of our prior decisions, the
Rule is therefore unconstitutional. |
[33] | Ms. Anastasoff's interpretation of § 7502 was directly
addressed and rejected in Christie. *fn15
Eighth Cir. R. 28A(i) does not free us from our obligation to follow
that decision. Accordingly, we affirm the judgment of the District
Court. |
[34] | HEANEY, Circuit Judge, concurring. |
[35] | I agree fully with Judge Arnold's opinion. He has done
the public, the court, and the bar a great service by writing so fully
and cogently on the precedential effect of unpublished opinions. I write
separately only to state that in my view, this is a case which should be
heard en banc in order to reconsider our holding in Christie, and thus
resolve an important issue. |
[36] | A true copy. |
[37] | Attest: |
[38] | CLERK, U.S. COURT OF APPEALS, EIGHTH CIRCUIT. |
Opinion Footnotes | |
[39] | *fn1 The Hon. Paul A. Magnuson, Chief Judge, United
States District Court for the District of Minnesota, sitting by
designation. |
[40] | *fn2
The Hon. Catherine D. Perry, United States District Judge for the
Eastern District of Missouri. |
[41] | *fn3
"The judicial Power of the United States, shall be vested in one
supreme Court, and in such inferior Courts as the Congress may from time
to time ordain and establish." U.S. Const. art. III, § 1, cl. 1. |
[42] | *fn4
Lawyers made up majorities of the Continental Congress, the signers of
the Declaration of Independence, and the Framers of the Constitution.
Perry Miller, The Legal Mind in America 16 (1962). |
[43] | *fn5
James Wilson suggested that the doctrine of precedent was brought to
England by the Romans. 1 The Works of James Wilson 343 (1967).
Chancellor Kent traced it "from the earliest periods of English
history." James Kent, Commentaries on American Law 473-78 (12th ed.
1873). Blackstone found it "even so early as the conquest." 1
William Blackstone, Commentaries *69. Before them, in Slade v. Morley,
Sir Edward Coke suggested simply that "precedents have always been
respected . . .." 4 Co. Rep. 91, 76 Eng. Rep. 1074 (K.B. 1602),
reprinted in Sources of English Legal History: Private Law to 1750 428
(1986). |
[44] | *fn6
Coke's struggle against the tyranny of the Stuarts, which the Framers
identified with their own against King George, made him the legal
authority most admired and most often cited by American patriots.
Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution 30
(1967). Coke used precedent, and emphasized it to a greater degree than
his predecessors, because it was his main weapon in the fight for the
independence of the judiciary and limits on the king's prerogative
rights. See Harold J. Berman and Charles J. Reid, Jr., The
Transformation of English Legal Science: From Hale to Blackstone, 45
Emory L.J. 437, 450 (1996); J.G.A. Pocock, The Ancient Constitution and
the Feudal Law 46 (1987). By contrast, the only criticism of the
doctrine of precedent was associated with Thomas Hobbes, who regarded
the authority of precedent as an affront to the absolute power of the
Sovereign. See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan 323-26 (Penguin ed. 1985). |
[45] | *fn7
See, e.g., Frederick Schauer, Precedent, 39 Stan. L. Rev. 571, 595-602
(1987) (noting that the authority of precedent is commonly supported by
arguments: (1) from fundamental fairness, i.e., that like cases should
be treated alike; (2) from the need for predictability; and (3) as an
aid to judicial decision-making, to prevent unnecessary reconsideration
of established matters). |
[46] | *fn8
Blackstone's great influence on the Framers' understanding of law is a
familiar fact. See Schick v. United States, 195 U.S. 65, 69 (1904)
("At the time of the adoption of the Federal Constitution, it
[Blackstone's work] had been published about twenty years, and it has
been said that more copies of the work had been sold in this country
than in England; so that undoubtedly, the framers of the Constitution
were familiar with it."); Daniel Boorstin, The Mysterious Science
of Law 265 (1941). |
[47] | *fn9
This need not be done by way of a reported opinion. The record of the
judicial proceedings and decision alone is sufficient evidence of the
legal principles necessary to support the decision to provide
"light or assistance" when "any critical question
arises." 1 Blackstone, Commentaries *69. |
[48] | *fn10
See Letter from James Madison to Charles Jared Ingersoll (June 25,
1831), reprinted in The Mind of the Founder: Sources of the Political
Thought of James Madison 390, 390-93 (Marvin Meyers ed., rev. ed. 1981)
(describing the "authoritative force" of "judicial
precedents" as stemming from the "obligations arising from
judicial expositions of the law on succeeding judges . . ..");
James Wilson, II The Works of James Wilson 502 (1967) ("Judicial
decisions are the principal and most authentick" proof of what the
law is and . . . "every prudent and cautious judge will appreciate
them [because] . . . his duty and his business is not to make the law,
but to interpret and apply it." Id. See also Christopher Wolfe, The
Rise of Modern Judicial Review: From Constitutional Interpretation to
Judge-Made Law 74 (1986); David M. O'Brien, Constitutional Law and
Politics 73 (1995). |
[49] | *fn11
James Wilson agreed: "judicium is quasi juris dictum . . . a
judgment is a declaration of the law." II The Works of James Wilson
524 (1967). |
[50] | *fn12
Other early authorities confirm the connection between the doctrine of
precedent and the separation of powers. See 1 Kent's Commentaries, Lect.
XXI at 479: "Those nations, which have adopted the civil law as the
main foundation of their own [recognize precedent to a far less degree
than our own] . . .. With them the necessity of judiciary independence
upon the executive, is not so clearly acknowledged . . .. It has been
shown already that this independence requires, in a considerable degree,
the acknowledgment of precedential authority."; William Cranch,
Preface, 1 Cranch iii (1804): "In a government which is
emphatically styled a government of laws, the least possible range ought
to be left for the discretion of the judge . . . perhaps nothing
conduces more to that object than the publication of reports. Every case
decided is a check upon the judge. He can not decide a similar case
differently, without strong reasons, which, for his own justification,
he will wish to make public." |
[51] | *fn13
See, e.g., Essays of Brutus, XV (Mar. 20, 1788) in 2 The Complete
Anti-Federalist, 441 (Herbert J. Storing ed., 1981): "one
adjudication will form a precedent to the next, and this to a following
one. These cases will immediately affect individuals only; so that a
series of determinations will probably take place before even the people
will be informed of them." By contrast, the danger in the Federal
Farmer's view was that the federal courts had "no precedents in
this country, as yet, to regulate the divisions in equity as in Great
Britain; equity, therefore, in the supreme court for many years will be
mere discretion." Letters from The Federal Farmer No. 3 (Oct. 10,
1787), in 2 The Complete Anti-Federalist at 244. |
[52] | *fn14
In this, they were following the common-law view, which considered entry
on the official court record sufficient to give a decision precedential
authority whether or not the decision was subsequently reported. See,
e.g., Coke, 2 Institutes, Proeme, last paragraph (stating that judicial
decisions are reliable authority whether they are published, i.e.,
"related and reported in our Bookes," or only "extant in
judicial Records . . .."). This remained true even after reporting
became more systematic. See James Ram, Science of Legal Judgment (1834)
("A manuscript note of a case is authority. It may be more full, or
accurate, than a printed report of the same case. The existence of such
manuscript may be little known. When cited by a party in a cause . . .
it may be 'an authority precisely applicable' (18 Ves. 347); but the
opposite party, or the Court, may never have heard of it before; it may
then come as a great surprise upon both."). |
[53] | *fn15
On July 28, 2000, the Second Circuit decided Weisbart v. United States
Dep't of Treasury, 2000 WL 1041231 (2d Cir. July 28, 2000). Weisbart
appears to conflict with Christie. We express no view on whether we
would follow Weisbart if it were not for the conclusive effect of
Christie. |